가톨릭 신앙생활 Q&A 코너

Ia IIae q91 법(law)의 종류들 - 필독 권고 [신학대전여행] 969_토미즘학습

인쇄

신학대전여행 [218.55.90.*]

2014-07-29 ㅣ No.1564

(십자성호를 그으며)
† 성부와 성자와 성령의 이름으로 아멘.

 

당부의 말씀:

많이 부족한 죄인인 필자의 글들은 어떤 특정인의 감정을 자극하기 위하여 마련된 글들이 결코 아니기에, 다음의 당부의 말씀을 드립니다:

(1) 지금까지 필자의 글들을 읽고서 필자에 대한 "분노(anger)" 혹은 "질투(envy)"를 가지게 된 분들은, 혹시라도 그분들께 "걸림돌(stumbling block)"일 수도 있는, 많이 부족한 죄인의 글들을 더 이상 읽지 마시기 바랍니다. 꼭 부탁드립니다.

(2) 그리고 위의 제(1)항의 당부의 말씀을 읽고도 굳이 이 화면의 아래로 스스로 이동하여, 많이 부족한 죄인의 아래의 본글을 읽는 분들은, 필자에 대한 "분노(anger)"와 "질투(envy)" 둘 다를 가지지 않을 것임에 동의함을 필자와 다른 분들께 이미 밝힌 것으로 이해하겠습니다.

(3) 그리 길지 않은 인생 여정에 있어, 누구에게나, 결국에, "유유상종[類類相從, 같은 무리끼리 서로 사귐 (출처: 표준국어대사전)]"이 유의미할 것이라는 생각에 드리는 당부의 말씀입니다.

 

  

+ 찬미 예수님!

 

 

게시자 주: 이번 글은, 다음의 주소에 있는 글 [제목: 자연법과 계시된 법(하느님의 [실정]법)의 차이점에 대하여]의 근거인, 대단히 중요한 내용의 글입니다. 국내의 성직자 및 수도자들을 포함하여, 되도록 많은 분들께서는, 이번 글뿐만이 아니라, 다음의 주소에 있는 글을 읽으실 것을 강력하게 권고드립니다:

http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/1207.htm <----- 필독 권고

 

번역자 주: 다음은, 성 토마스 아퀴나스의 신학 대전의 약 600여 개에 달하는 각 문항(Questions)들에 대한 "압축된 바꾸어 말하기"인 Paul J. Glenn 몬시뇰(1893-1957)의 저서: "A Tour of the Summa(신학대전여행)"의 Ia IIae, q91, 법의 종류들 전문이며, 그리고 하반부의 글은, 상반부의 글에 대응하는 성 토마스 아퀴나스의 신학 대전, Ia IIae, q91, 법의 종류들 전문이다.

초벌 번역 일자: 2014년7월 25
번역자: 교수 소순태 마태오 (Ph.D.)
우리말 번역문 출처: 
http://club.catholic.or.kr/tourofsumma
본글로의 접속 주소: http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/1564.htm
--------------------
 
91. Kinds of Law

 

91. 법의 종류들

 

1. The community of all things in the universe is governed by divine reason. This government is law. Since divine reason is eternal, being identified with God himself, this law is the eternal law.

 

1. 우주에 있는 모든 사물들로 이루어진 공동체는 신성적 이성(divine reason)에 의하여 통치됩니다. 바로 이 통치가 법(法, law)입니다. 신성적 이성은 영원하기 때문에, 하느님 당신 자신과 동일시 되어, 바로 이 법이 영원한 법(the eternal law)입니다.(*)

 

-----
(*) 번역자 주: 여기서 "법(法, law)" 이라는 용어의 정의(definition)와 이 용어와 논리적으로 등가의 의미를 가지는 "영원한 법[the eternal law, 영항율(永恒律)]" 라는 용어의 정의(definition)가 주어지고 있다.
-----

 

2. All things are subject to the eternal law; it directs all things to their proper ends. But it is, in a special way, the law which governs rational creatures. Human beings share the divine reason by becoming aware of an order in things according to which man is to attain his last end, his true purpose in existing. The eternal law, thus manifest to human reason, is called the natural law. The natural law is the eternal moral law as knowable by sound human reason without the aid of supernatural revelation.

 

2. 모든 사물들은 영원한 법에 종속하며(subject to), 그리고 이 법은 모든 사물들을 그들의 고유한 끝(end, 목표) 쪽으로 향하게 합니다(directs). 그러나 이 법은, 어떤 특별한 방식으로, 이성을 가진 피조물(rational creatures)들을 통치하는 바로 그 법입니다. 인간들은, 그것에 따라 사람이 자신의 마지막 끝/최종 대상(last end)을, 존재함에 있어 자신의 참된 목적을 획득하는, 사물들에 있는 한 질서(an order)에 대하여 알아차리게 됨으로써 이 신성적 이성(the divine reason)에 참여합니다(share, participate in).(*) 바로 이러한 방식으로 인간의 이성에 분명히 나타난(manifest) 영원한 법은 자연법(the natural law)이라고 불립니다.(**) 자연법은, 초자연적 계시의 도움 없이, 건전한(sound) 인간의 이성에 의하여 알 수 있는 것으로서(as knowable) 영원한 윤리법(the eternal moral law)입니다.

 

-----
(*) 번역자 주: "참여하다(participate)" 라는 용어의 정의(definition)는 다음에 있다:
http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/1585_participate.htm


(**) 번역자 주: 여기서 "자연법(the natural law)" 이라는 용어의 정의(definition)가 주어지고 있다.
-----

 

3. From the precepts of the natural law, human reason derives details of direction and order for conducting the affairs of life. Human reason interprets or applies the natural law in particular cases. Each enactment and application of the natural law for particular cases is a human law.

 

3. 이 자연법의 규범들로부터, 인간의 이성(human reason)은 삶의 일들을 수행하기 위한 방향과 질서의 세부 사항들을 도출합니다. 인간의 이성은 이 자연법을 특정한 경우들에 있어 해석하거나 혹는 적용합니다. 이 자연법의 각 법규(enactment)와 적용은 한 개의 인정법(a human law, 人定法)입니다.(*)

 

-----
(*) 번역자 주: 여기서 "인정법[human law, 人定法, 인법(人法)]" 이라는 용어의 정의(definition)이 주어지고 있다.
-----

 

4. Over and above the natural law, and human laws derived from it, man needs to have the eternal and divine law revealed to him supernaturally. For man has a supernatural end to attain; merely natural means are inadequate to attain this end. Besides, human judgment about particular acts and situations is variable and uncertain, so that human laws are sometimes contrary to one another. Nothing short of an unmistakable declaration of divine and eternal law can adequately direct and curb the interior acts of a man. Such declaration is made only by supernatural revelation. Human laws cannot forbid and punish all evils; when human laws attempt to do this, they invariably destroy much that is good. Only the divine law, supernaturally manifested, can forbid and punish all evils, and at the same time perfectly serve the common good of human society.

 

4. 이 자연법, 그리고 이 법으로부터 도출되는 인정법, 위에 그리고 넘어서, 사람은 초자연적으로 그에게 계시된(revealed) 영원한 그리고 신성적 법(the eternal and divine law)(*)을 가질 필요가 있습니다. 이는 사람이 획득하고자 하는 한 초자연적 끝(supernatural end)을 가지고 있으며, 그리고 단순히 자연적 수단들은 바로 이 끝(end)을 획득하는 데에 충분하지 않기(inadequate) 때문입니다. 게다가, 특정한 행위들과 상황들에 관한 인간의 판단은 가변적이고(variable) 그리고 불확실하여(uncertain), 그리하여 그 결과 인정법(human laws)들은 때로는 서로 상반됩니다. 신성적 그리고 영원한 법의 한 혼동할 수 없는 선언의 아무런 부족함이 없음은 한 사람의 내면적 행위들을 충분하게(adequately) 지시할(direct) 수 있고 그리고 억제할(curb) 수 있습니다. 그러한 선언은 오로지 초자연적 계시(supernatural revelation)에 의하여서만 마련됩니다. 인정법(人定法)들은 모든 악(evils)들을 금지할 수 없고 그리고 벌할 수 없으며, 인정법들이 이것을 시도할 때에, 그들은 반드시(invariably) 선한(good) 많은 것을 파괴합니다. 오로지, 초자연적으로 분명하게 나타내어진(manifested) 신성적 법(the divine law)만이 모든 악(evils)들을 금지할 수 있고 그리고 벌할 수 있으며, 그리고 동시에 완미하게(perfectly) 인간 사회의 공동선에 도움이 될 수 있습니다.

 

-----
(*) 번역자 주:
(1) 다음의 신학 대전 Ia IIae, q91 의 요약문에 의하면, "신성적 그리고 계시된 법(the divine and revealed law)" 이라는 표현 자체가, "신성적 법(the divine law, 신법)" = "계시된 법(the revealed law, 계시법)" 과 논리적으로 등가임을 알 수 있다:
http://www3.nd.edu/~afreddos/courses/406/law.htm

 

(2) 그리고 다음의 동영상들을 또한 참고하라 [구글 검색 key words: "divine law" "eternal law" "human law" "natural law" 'Philosophy Core Concepts" "Gregory B. Sadler"]:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=J40YZ49oJQg
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=FlQLgiWs_mw
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=bWSfi51PVNM
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Rh1CMXaB8xg (1:43:30)
-----

 

5. The divine and revealed law is manifested in the Old and the New Testaments of Holy Scripture. We call these the Old Law and the New Law. These two laws are distinct, as the imperfect state of a thing is distinct from its fully developed and perfect state; as the baby is distinct from the adult into which it is developing; as the sapling is distinct from the tree that it is to become. For the New Law is the perfection of the Old Law. The Old Law worked for the good of mankind through material things; the New Law works for the good of mankind through spiritual things. The Old Law was enforced by fear; the New Law is enforced by love.

 

5. 신성적 그리고 계시된 법(the divine and revealed law)은 성경 본문의 구약 및 신약들에서 분명하게 드러나게 됩니다. 우리는 이들을 옛 법(the Old Law) 그리고 새 법(the New Law) 이라고 부릅니다.(*) 이들 두 법들은, 한 사물의 불완미한 상태(imperfect state)가 그것의 충분하게 발전된 그리하여 완미한 상태와 다르듯이, 그리고 아기가, 바로 그 안쪽으로 이 아기가 성장하는, 어른(adult)과 다르듯이, 그리고 묘목(sapling)이, 이 묘목이 장차 될 나무와 다르듯이, 서로 다릅니다(distinct). 왜냐하면 새 법이 옛 법의 완미(perfection)이기 때문입니다. 옛 법은 질료적 사물들을 통하여 인류의 선을 위하여 일하였으며, 그리고 새 법은 영적인 사불들을 통하여 인류의 선을 위하여 일합니다. 옛 법은 두려움(fear)에 의하여 강요되었으나(was enforced), 그러나 새 법은 사랑(love, 애덕)에 의하여 강제됩니다.

 

-----

(*) 번역자 주: (1) 다음의 주소에 접속하면, Modern Catholic Dictionary에 주어진 "New Law"(새 법)의 설명을 학습할 수 있다:

http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/1562.htm <----- 필독 권고

 

(2) 그리고 다음의 주소에 접속하면, "하느님의 뜻/의도와 예수님의 새 계명은 동일하다(identical)" 제목의 졸고[게시일자: 2023-12-20] 등을 읽을 수 있다. 필독을 권고드린다:

http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/하느님의_의도와_예수님의_새_계명은_동일하다_1562.htm <----- 꼭 필독 권고

-----

  

6. By sin, man turned away from God and fell under the influence of strong sensual impulses. These impulses are always ready to flame up instantly; they are called fomes of sin. Fomes is the Latin word for touchwood or tinder that catches fire from the smallest spark. Now, while fomes is a deviation from the rule of reason, it is a constant directive force, and therefore it is called (though not with strict propriety) a law. St. Paul speaks of it so when he says (Bom. 7:23): "I see another law in my members fighting against the law of my mind."

 

6. 죄에 의하여, 사람은 하느님을 외면하였고 그리하여 강한 감각적인 충동들의 영향 아래로 떨어졌습니다. 이러한 충동들은 항상 즉각 확 타오르는 것을 기꺼이 하며, 그리하여 그들은 죄의 매개물(fomes)이라고 불립니다. 매개믈(fomes)은, 가장 작은 불꽃으로부터 불을 붙잡는(catch fire) 부싯깃으로 쓰는 썩은 나무(touchwood) 혹은 부싯깃(tinder, 불이 붙기 쉬운 것)를 나타내는 라틴어 단어입니다. 그런데, 매개물(fomes)이 이성의 지배로부터 한 파생어(a derivation)라고 하더라도, 이 단어는 한 개의 지속하는 지시하는 힘(directive force)이고, 그리하여 그 결과 이것은 [비록 엄밀한 적절성(propriety)과 함께가 아님에도 불구하고] 한 개의 법(a law)이라고 불립니다. 성 바오로(St. Paul)는 이것에 대하여, 그가 다음과 같이 말할 때에, 그렇게 말합니다: "내 지체 안에 다른 법이 있어 내 이성의 법과 대결하고 있음을 나는 봅니다" (로마 7,23).

 

----------

영어본 원문 출처: http://www.catholictheology.info/summa-theologica/summa-part2A.php?q=593

 

====================

 

출처 1: http://www.newadvent.org/summa/2091.htm
출처 2: http://www.intratext.com/IXT/ENG0023/__P6Z.HTM

 

신학 대전 Ia IIae

 

Question 91. The various kinds of law

 

We must now consider the various kinds of law: under which head there are six points of inquiry:

 

우리는 이제 법(law)의 다양한 종류들에 대하여 고찰하여야 하며, 그리고 이 표제 아래에서 질문에 있어서의 여섯 개의 요지들이 다음과 같이 있습니다:

 

1. Is there an eternal law?
2. Is there a natural law?
3. Is there a human law?
4. Is there a Divine law?
5. Is there one Divine law, or several?
6. Is there a law of sin?

 

Article 1. Whether there is an eternal law?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there is no eternal law. Because every law is imposed on someone. But there was not someone from eternity on whom a law could be imposed: since God alone was from eternity. Therefore no law is eternal.

 

Objection 2. Further, promulgation is essential to law. But promulgation could not be from eternity: because there was no one to whom it could be promulgated from eternity. Therefore no law can be eternal.

 

Objection 3. Further, a law implies order to an end. But nothing ordained to an end is eternal: for the last end alone is eternal. Therefore no law is eternal.

 

On the contrary, Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. i, 6): "That Law which is the Supreme Reason cannot be understood to be otherwise than unchangeable and eternal."

 

I answer that, As stated above (90, 1, ad 2; A3,4), a law is nothing else but a dictate of practical reason emanating from the ruler who governs a perfect community. Now it is evident, granted that the world is ruled by Divine Providence, as was stated in the I, 22, A1,2, that the whole community of the universe is governed by Divine Reason. Wherefore the very Idea of the government of things in God the Ruler of the universe, has the nature of a law. And since the Divine Reason's conception of things is not subject to time but is eternal, according to Proverbs 8:23, therefore it is that this kind of law must be called eternal.

 

Reply to Objection 1. Those things that are not in themselves, exist with God, inasmuch as they are foreknown and preordained by Him, according to Romans 4:17: "Who calls those things that are not, as those that are." Accordingly the eternal concept of the Divine law bears the character of an eternal law, in so far as it is ordained by God to the government of things foreknown by Him.

 

Reply to Objection 2. Promulgation is made by word of mouth or in writing; and in both ways the eternal law is promulgated: because both the Divine Word and the writing of the Book of Life are eternal. But the promulgation cannot be from eternity on the part of the creature that hears or reads.

 

Reply to Objection 3. The law implies order to the end actively, in so far as it directs certain things to the end; but not passively--that is to say, the law itself is not ordained to the end--except accidentally, in a governor whose end is extrinsic to him, and to which end his law must needs be ordained. But the end of the Divine government is God Himself, and His law is not distinct from Himself. Wherefore the eternal law is not ordained to another end.

 

Article 2. Whether there is in us a natural law?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there is no natural law in us. Because man is governed sufficiently by the eternal law: for Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. i) that "the eternal law is that by which it is right that all things should be most orderly." But nature does not abound in superfluities as neither does she fail in necessaries. Therefore no law is natural to man.

 

Objection 2. Further, by the law man is directed, in his acts, to the end, as stated above (Question 90, Article 2). But the directing of human acts to their end is not a function of nature, as is the case in irrational creatures, which act for an end solely by their natural appetite; whereas man acts for an end by his reason and will. Therefore no law is natural to man.

 

Objection 3. Further, the more a man is free, the less is he under the law. But man is freer than all the animals, on account of his free-will, with which he is endowed above all other animals. Since therefore other animals are not subject to a natural law, neither is man subject to a natural law.

 

On the contrary, A gloss on Romans 2:14: "When the Gentiles, who have not the law, do by nature those things that are of the law," comments as follows: "Although they have no written law, yet they have the natural law, whereby each one knows, and is conscious of, what is good and what is evil."

 

I answer that, As stated above (90, 1, ad 1), law, being a rule and measure, can be in a person in two ways: in one way, as in him that rules and measures; in another way, as in that which is ruled and measured, since a thing is ruled and measured, in so far as it partakes of the rule or measure. Wherefore, since all things subject to Divine providence are ruled and measured by the eternal law, as was stated above (Article 1); it is evident that all things partake somewhat of the eternal law, in so far as, namely, from its being imprinted on them, they derive their respective inclinations to their proper acts and ends. Now among all others, the rational creature is subject to Divine providence in the most excellent way, in so far as it partakes of a share of providence, by being provident both for itself and for others. Wherefore it has a share of the Eternal Reason, whereby it has a natural inclination to its proper act and end: and this participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is called the natural law. Hence the Psalmist after saying (Psalm 4:6): "Offer up the sacrifice of justice," as though someone asked what the works of justice are, adds: "Many say, Who showeth us good things?" in answer to which question he says: "The light of Thy countenance, O Lord, is signed upon us": thus implying that the light of natural reason, whereby we discern what is good and what is evil, which is the function of the natural law, is nothing else than an imprint on us of the Divine light. It is therefore evident that the natural law is nothing else than the rational creature's participation of the eternal law.

 

Reply to Objection 1. This argument would hold, if the natural law were something different from the eternal law: whereas it is nothing but a participation thereof, as stated above.

 

Reply to Objection 2. Every act of reason and will in us is based on that which is according to nature, as stated above (Question 10, Article 1): for every act of reasoning is based on principles that are known naturally, and every act of appetite in respect of the means is derived from the natural appetite in respect of the last end. Accordingly the first direction of our acts to their end must needs be in virtue of the natural law.

 

Reply to Objection 3. Even irrational animals partake in their own way of the Eternal Reason, just as the rational creature does. But because the rational creature partakes thereof in an intellectual and rational manner, therefore the participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is properly called a law, since a law is something pertaining to reason, as stated above (Question 90, Article 1). Irrational creatures, however, do not partake thereof in a rational manner, wherefore there is no participation of the eternal law in them, except by way of similitude.

 

Article 3. Whether there is a human law?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there is not a human law. For the natural law is a participation of the eternal law, as stated above (Article 2). Now through the eternal law "all things are most orderly," as Augustine states (De Lib. Arb. i, 6). Therefore the natural law suffices for the ordering of all human affairs. Consequently there is no need for a human law.

 

Objection 2. Further, a law bears the character of a measure, as stated above (Question 90, Article 1). But human reason is not a measure of things, but vice versa, as stated in Metaph. x, text. 5. Therefore no law can emanate from human reason.

 

Objection 3. Further, a measure should be most certain, as stated in Metaph. x, text. 3. But the dictates of human reason in matters of conduct are uncertain, according to Wisdom 9:14: "The thoughts of mortal men are fearful, and our counsels uncertain." Therefore no law can emanate from human reason.

 

On the contrary, Augustine (De Lib. Arb. i, 6) distinguishes two kinds of law, the one eternal, the other temporal, which he calls human.

 

I answer that, As stated above (90, 1, ad 2), a law is a dictate of the practical reason. Now it is to be observed that the same procedure takes place in the practical and in the speculative reason: for each proceeds from principles to conclusions, as stated above (De Lib. Arb. i, 6). Accordingly we conclude that just as, in the speculative reason, from naturally known indemonstrable principles, we draw the conclusions of the various sciences, the knowledge of which is not imparted to us by nature, but acquired by the efforts of reason, so too it is from the precepts of the natural law, as from general and indemonstrable principles, that the human reason needs to proceed to the more particular determination of certain matters. These particular determinations, devised by human reason, are called human laws, provided the other essential conditions of law be observed, as stated above (90, A2,3,4). Wherefore Tully says in his Rhetoric (De Invent. Rhet. ii) that "justice has its source in nature; thence certain things came into custom by reason of their utility; afterwards these things which emanated from nature and were approved by custom, were sanctioned by fear and reverence for the law."

 

Reply to Objection 1. The human reason cannot have a full participation of the dictate of the Divine Reason, but according to its own mode, and imperfectly. Consequently, as on the part of the speculative reason, by a natural participation of Divine Wisdom, there is in us the knowledge of certain general principles, but not proper knowledge of each single truth, such as that contained in the Divine Wisdom; so too, on the part of the practical reason, man has a natural participation of the eternal law, according to certain general principles, but not as regards the particular determinations of individual cases, which are, however, contained in the eternal law. Hence the need for human reason to proceed further to sanction them by law.

 

Reply to Objection 2. Human reason is not, of itself, the rule of things: but the principles impressed on it by nature, are general rules and measures of all things relating to human conduct, whereof the natural reason is the rule and measure, although it is not the measure of things that are from nature.

 

Reply to Objection 3. The practical reason is concerned with practical matters, which are singular and contingent: but not with necessary things, with which the speculative reason is concerned. Wherefore human laws cannot have that inerrancy that belongs to the demonstrated conclusions of sciences. Nor is it necessary for every measure to be altogether unerring and certain, but according as it is possible in its own particular genus.

 

Article 4. Whether there was any need for a Divine law?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there was no need for a Divine law. Because, as stated above (Article 2), the natural law is a participation in us of the eternal law. But the eternal law is a Divine law, as stated above (Article 1). Therefore there was no need for a Divine law in addition to the natural law, and human laws derived therefrom.

 

Objection 2. Further, it is written (Sirach 15:14) that "God left man in the hand of his own counsel." Now counsel is an act of reason, as stated above (Question 14, Article 1). Therefore man was left to the direction of his reason. But a dictate of human reason is a human law as stated above (Article 3). Therefore there is no need for man to be governed also by a Divine law.

 

Objection 3. Further, human nature is more self-sufficing than irrational creatures. But irrational creatures have no Divine law besides the natural inclination impressed on them. Much less, therefore, should the rational creature have a Divine law in addition to the natural law.

 

On the contrary, David prayed God to set His law before him, saying (Psalm 118:33): "Set before me for a law the way of Thy justifications, O Lord."

 

I answer that, Besides the natural and the human law it was necessary for the directing of human conduct to have a Divine law. And this for four reasons. First, because it is by law that man is directed how to perform his proper acts in view of his last end. And indeed if man were ordained to no other end than that which is proportionate to his natural faculty, there would be no need for man to have any further direction of the part of his reason, besides the natural law and human law which is derived from it. But since man is ordained to an end of eternal happiness which is inproportionate to man's natural faculty, as stated above (Question 5, Article 5), therefore it was necessary that, besides the natural and the human law, man should be directed to his end by a law given by God.

 

Secondly, because, on account of the uncertainty of human judgment, especially on contingent and particular matters, different people form different judgments on human acts; whence also different and contrary laws result. In order, therefore, that man may know without any doubt what he ought to do and what he ought to avoid, it was necessary for man to be directed in his proper acts by a law given by God, for it is certain that such a law cannot err.

 

두 번째로, 특히 [변성(變成)함에 있어 연(緣)이] 비필연적(非必然的)인(contingent)(*) 그리고 개별적인 사안(matter)들에 대한 인간의 판단의 불확실성의 이유로, 인간의 행위들에 대하여 서로 다른 사람들이 서로 다른 판단들을 형성하고, 그리고 거기로부터 또한 서로 다른 그리고 상반되는 법들이 결과로서 생기기(result) 때문입니다. 그러므로, 사람이 아무런 의심 없이 자신이 당연히 행하여야(do) 하는 바를 그리고 그가 당연히 피하여야(avoid) 하는 바를 알기 위하여, 사람이 하느님에 의하여 주어진 어떤 법 [즉, 신성적 법(divine law), 신법, 계시된 법(revealed law), 계시법]에 의하여 자신의 고유한 행위들에 있어 명령을 받는(be directed) 것은 필요하였는데, 이는 그러한 법이 틀릴(err) 수가 없다는 것은 확실하기 때문입니다. 

 

-----

(*) 번역자 주: "[변성(變成)함에 있어 연(緣)이] 비필연적(非必然的)인(contingent)" 이라는 용어의 정의(definition)는 다음의 글에 있으니 필독하라:

http://ch.catholic.or.kr/pundang/4/soh/1554.htm

----- 

 

Thirdly, because man can make laws in those matters of which he is competent to judge. But man is not competent to judge of interior movements, that are hidden, but only of exterior acts which appear: and yet for the perfection of virtue it is necessary for man to conduct himself aright in both kinds of acts. Consequently human law could not sufficiently curb and direct interior acts; and it was necessary for this purpose that a Divine law should supervene.

 

Fourthly, because, as Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. i, 5,6), human law cannot punish or forbid all evil deeds: since while aiming at doing away with all evils, it would do away with many good things, and would hinder the advance of the common good, which is necessary for human intercourse. In order, therefore, that no evil might remain unforbidden and unpunished, it was necessary for the Divine law to supervene, whereby all sins are forbidden.

 

And these four causes are touched upon in Psalm 118:8, where it is said: "The law of the Lord is unspotted," i.e. allowing no foulness of sin; "converting souls," because it directs not only exterior, but also interior acts; "the testimony of the Lord is faithful," because of the certainty of what is true and right; "giving wisdom to little ones," by directing man to an end supernatural and Divine.

 

Reply to Objection 1. By the natural law the eternal law is participated proportionately to the capacity of human nature. But to his supernatural end man needs to be directed in a yet higher way. Hence the additional law given by God, whereby man shares more perfectly in the eternal law.

 

Reply to Objection 2. Counsel is a kind of inquiry: hence it must proceed from some principles. Nor is it enough for it to proceed from principles imparted by nature, which are the precepts of the natural law, for the reasons given above: but there is need for certain additional principles, namely, the precepts of the Divine law.

 

Reply to Objection 3. Irrational creatures are not ordained to an end higher than that which is proportionate to their natural powers: consequently the comparison fails.

 

Article 5. Whether there is but one Divine law?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there is but one Divine law. Because, where there is one king in one kingdom there is but one law. Now the whole of mankind is compared to God as to one king, according to Psalm 46:8: "God is the King of all the earth." Therefore there is but one Divine law.

 

Objection 2. Further, every law is directed to the end which the lawgiver intends for those for whom he makes the law. But God intends one and the same thing for all men; since according to 1 Timothy 2:4: "He will have all men to be saved, and to come to the knowledge of the truth." Therefore there is but one Divine law.

 

Objection 3. Further, the Divine law seems to be more akin to the eternal law, which is one, than the natural law, according as the revelation of grace is of a higher order than natural knowledge. Therefore much more is the Divine law but one.

 

On the contrary, The Apostle says (Hebrews 7:12): "The priesthood being translated, it is necessary that a translation also be made of the law." But the priesthood is twofold, as stated in the same passage, viz. the levitical priesthood, and the priesthood of Christ. Therefore the Divine law is twofold, namely the Old Law and the New Law.

 

I answer that, As stated in the I, 30, 3, distinction is the cause of number. Now things may be distinguished in two ways. First, as those things that are altogether specifically different, e.g. a horse and an ox. Secondly, as perfect and imperfect in the same species, e.g. a boy and a man: and in this way the Divine law is divided into Old and New. Hence the Apostle (Galatians 3:24-25) compares the state of man under the Old Law to that of a child "under a pedagogue"; but the state under the New Law, to that of a full grown man, who is "no longer under a pedagogue."

 

Now the perfection and imperfection of these two laws is to be taken in connection with the three conditions pertaining to law, as stated above. For, in the first place, it belongs to law to be directed to the common good as to its end, as stated above (Question 90, Article 2). This good may be twofold. It may be a sensible and earthly good; and to this, man was directly ordained by the Old Law: wherefore, at the very outset of the law, the people were invited to the earthly kingdom of the Chananaeans (Exodus 3:8-17). Again it may be an intelligible and heavenly good: and to this, man is ordained by the New Law. Wherefore, at the very beginning of His preaching, Christ invited men to the kingdom of heaven, saying (Matthew 4:17): "Do penance, for the kingdom of heaven is at hand." Hence Augustine says (Contra Faust. iv) that "promises of temporal goods are contained in the Old Testament, for which reason it is called old; but the promise of eternal life belongs to the New Testament."

 

Secondly, it belongs to the law to direct human acts according to the order of righteousness (4): wherein also the New Law surpasses the Old Law, since it directs our internal acts, according to Matthew 5:20: "Unless your justice abound more than that of the Scribes and Pharisees, you shall not enter into the kingdom of heaven." Hence the saying that "the Old Law restrains the hand, but the New Law controls the mind" ( Sentent. iii, D, xl).

 

Thirdly, it belongs to the law to induce men to observe its commandments. This the Old Law did by the fear of punishment: but the New Law, by love, which is poured into our hearts by the grace of Christ, bestowed in the New Law, but foreshadowed in the Old. Hence Augustine says (Contra Adimant. Manich. discip. xvii) that "there is little difference [The 'little difference' refers to the Latin words 'timor' and 'amor'--'fear' and 'love.'] between the Law and the Gospel--fear and love."

 

Reply to Objection 1. As the father of a family issues different commands to the children and to the adults, so also the one King, God, in His one kingdom, gave one law to men, while they were yet imperfect, and another more perfect law, when, by the preceding law, they had been led to a greater capacity for Divine things.

 

Reply to Objection 2. The salvation of man could not be achieved otherwise than through Christ, according to Acts 4:12: "There is no other name . . . given to men, whereby we must be saved." Consequently the law that brings all to salvation could not be given until after the coming of Christ. But before His coming it was necessary to give to the people, of whom Christ was to be born, a law containing certain rudiments of righteousness unto salvation, in order to prepare them to receive Him.

 

Reply to Objection 3. The natural law directs man by way of certain general precepts, common to both the perfect and the imperfect: wherefore it is one and the same for all. But the Divine law directs man also in certain particular matters, to which the perfect and imperfect do not stand in the same relation. Hence the necessity for the Divine law to be twofold, as already explained.

 

Article 6. Whether there is a law in the fomes of sin?

 

Objection 1. It would seem that there is no law of the "fomes" of sin. For Isidore says (Etym. v) that the "law is based on reason." But the "fomes" of sin is not based on reason, but deviates from it. Therefore the "fomes" has not the nature of a law.

 

Objection 2. Further, every law is binding, so that those who do not obey it are called transgressors. But man is not called a transgressor, from not following the instigations of the "fomes"; but rather from his following them. Therefore the "fomes" has not the nature of a law.

 

Objection 3. Further, the law is ordained to the common good, as stated above (Question 90, Article 2). But the "fomes" inclines us, not to the common, but to our own private good. Therefore the "fomes" has not the nature of sin.

 

On the contrary, The Apostle says (Romans 7:23): "I see another law in my members, fighting against the law of my mind."

 

I answer that, As stated above (2; 90, 1, ad 1), the law, as to its essence, resides in him that rules and measures; but, by way of participation, in that which is ruled and measured; so that every inclination or ordination which may be found in things subject to the law, is called a law by participation, as stated above (2; 90, 1, ad 1). Now those who are subject to a law may receive a twofold inclination from the lawgiver. First, in so far as he directly inclines his subjects to something; sometimes indeed different subjects to different acts; in this way we may say that there is a military law and a mercantile law. Secondly, indirectly; thus by the very fact that a lawgiver deprives a subject of some dignity, the latter passes into another order, so as to be under another law, as it were: thus if a soldier be turned out of the army, he becomes a subject of rural or of mercantile legislation.

 

Accordingly under the Divine Lawgiver various creatures have various natural inclinations, so that what is, as it were, a law for one, is against the law for another: thus I might say that fierceness is, in a way, the law of a dog, but against the law of a sheep or another meek animal. And so the law of man, which, by the Divine ordinance, is allotted to him, according to his proper natural condition, is that he should act in accordance with reason: and this law was so effective in the primitive state, that nothing either beside or against reason could take man unawares. But when man turned his back on God, he fell under the influence of his sensual impulses: in fact this happens to each one individually, the more he deviates from the path of reason, so that, after a fashion, he is likened to the beasts that are led by the impulse of sensuality, according to Psalm 48:21: "Man, when he was in honor, did not understand: he hath been compared to senseless beasts, and made like to them."

 

So, then, this very inclination of sensuality which is called the "fomes," in other animals has simply the nature of a law (yet only in so far as a law may be said to be in such things), by reason of a direct inclination. But in man, it has not the nature of law in this way, rather is it a deviation from the law of reason. But since, by the just sentence of God, man is destitute of original justice, and his reason bereft of its vigor, this impulse of sensuality, whereby he is led, in so far as it is a penalty following from the Divine law depriving man of his proper dignity, has the nature of a law.

 

Reply to Objection 1. This argument considers the "fomes" in itself, as an incentive to evil. It is not thus that it has the nature of a law, as stated above, but according as it results from the justice of the Divine law: it is as though we were to say that the law allows a nobleman to be condemned to hard labor for some misdeed.

 

Reply to Objection 2. This argument considers law in the light of a rule or measure: for it is in this sense that those who deviate from the law become transgressors. But the "fomes" is not a law in this respect, but by a kind of participation, as stated above.

 

Reply to Objection 3. This argument considers the "fomes" as to its proper inclination, and not as to its origin. And yet if the inclination of sensuality be considered as it is in other animals, thus it is ordained to the common good, namely, to the preservation of nature in the species or in the individual. And this is in man also, in so far as sensuality is subject to reason. But it is called "fomes" in so far as it strays from the order of reason.

 



982 1

추천

 

페이스북 트위터 핀터레스트 구글플러스

Comments
Total0
※ 500자 이내로 작성 가능합니다. (0/500)

  • ※ 로그인 후 등록 가능합니다.